Rank aggregation basics: Local Kemeny optimisation

The technical content of this post is based heavily on Rank Aggregation Revisited” by Ravi Kuma, Moni Naorz, D. Sivakumarx and Cynthia Dwork. It’s purely expository in nature on top of that.

You’ve all seen Hammer Principle now, right? If not, go check it out.

The task it performs of aggregating all the individual opinions into a single overall ranking is harder than it looks. This is a post about some of the technical details involved.

The setup is as follows: We have a bunch of items, and a bunch of votes placing a subset of those items in order.

The naive idea one starts with is as follows: If the majority of people prefer A to B, rank A higher than B. This is an obvious thing to aim for. Unfortunately it’s impossible, even if everyone ranks every item. Considering the following set of votes:

1: A, B, C
2: B, C, A
3: C, A, B

Then 1 and 3 think A < B, 1 and 2 think B < C, and 2 and 3 think C < A. So if we tried to order by majority opinion we'd have A < B < C < A. This is called Condorcet's paradox: Majority voting amongst > 2 items is impossible.

Nevertheless, we hope to be able to do at least reasonably well.

One natural approach is called Kemeny optimisation: We try to find a solution which minimizes the number of pairwise disagreements between the end rank and the individual voters. That is, for some set of items I, votes V and an aggregate ranking r, the score is

K(r) = #{ i, j in I, v in V, (r(i) < r(j)) != (v(i) < v(j)) } If r is a minimum for this score we say it's Kemeny optimal. There needn't be a unique Kemeny optimal solution: In the above example, all three of the individual votes are Kemeny optimal rankings. Kemeny optimal rankings have the following nice majority voting property: Let r be Kemeny optimal. If U and V partition the set of items, and for every u in U and v in V the majority think u < v, then for every u in U and v in V r(u) < r(v). Proof: Suppose we had r(u) > r(v) for some u, v. By passing to a smaler u and a larger v we can ensure that there is no z with r(u) > r(z) > r(v). (we can take the smallest u such that r(u) > r(v) then the largest v such that r(u) > r(v)).

But then if we were to define the ranking r’ which is exactly r except that u and v were swapped, this would decrease K: Because there are no points between them, the only pairwise disagreements it changes are those on u and v, so K(r’) – K(r) = #{ t : t(u) < t(v) } - #{ t : t(u) > t(v)}. But we know the majority think u < v, so this change in score must be negative, so we have K(r') < K(r), contradicting minimality. QED We call the conclusion of this theorem the generalised Condorcet criterion (the condorcet criterion is that if there's a single element that beats all the others in a majority vote then it should be the winner). It's a nice property - it is in some sense an approximation of majority voting. In many cases satisfying it will uniquely determine a great deal about the resulting ranking - it's only when there's ambiguity (as in the Condorcet paradox example) that it fails to do so. This should give us confidence that the Kemeny optimal solution is the right approach. So, we want to calculate a kemeny optimal solution. There's just one problem: We've defined the problem in terms of a minimization over all rankings of n items, of which there are n!. This search space is, to borrow a technical term, freaking huge. This makes it a hard problem. In fact finding a Kemeny optimal solution for rankings on n items is NP hard, even with only four votes. I won't prove this here. Read the paper if you care. So, no Kemeny optimal solutions for us. How sad. What would work well as a substitute? Well, examining our proof that Kemeny optimal solutions satisfy the generalised Condorcet condition, an interesting feature appears: We don't actually use anywhere that it is a global minimum. We only use the fact that swapping two adjacent pairs can’t decrease the score. This suggests the following relaxation of the condition:

A ranking r is locally Kemeny optimal if swapping two adjacent elements of the ranking does not decrease K.

By the above observation, locally Kemeny optimal solutions satisfy the generalized Condorcet condition.

This turns our problem from a global search to a local one: Basically we can start from any point in the search space and search locally by swapping adjacent pairs until we hit a minimum. This turns out to be quite easy to do. We basically run insertion sort: At step n we have the first n items in a locally Kemeny optimal order. Swap the n+1th item backwards until the majority think its predecessor is < it. This ensures all adjacent pairs are in the majority order, so swapping them would result in a greater than or equal K. This is of course an O(n^2) algorithm. In fact, the problem of merely finding a locally Kemeny optimal solution can be done in O(n log(n)) (for much the same reason as you can sort better than insertion sort). You just take the directed graph of majority votes and find a Hamiltonian Path. The nice thing about the above version of the algorithm is that it gives you a lot of control over where you start your search.

The above algorithm however produces an ordering which is consistent with its starting point in the following sense:

If we start with a ranking r and then run the above algorithm on it to get a ranking r’, then if r'(u) < r'(v) we must have r(u) < r(v) or a majority vote that u < v. This is easy to see: If r(u) > r(v) and the majority think that u > v then when moving u backwards we would have to stop at v at the latest.

In fact for any starting point there is only one kemeny optimal solution which is consistent for it in this way: We can see this inductively. If it’s true for the first n – 1 items, then where can we put the nth item? The only possible place is where the above algorithm puts it: If it were to put it after that place, it wouldn’t be Kemeny optimal. If it were to put it before it, it wouldn’t be consistent because it would be less than some item which it was greater than in the original ordering.

The unique locally Kemeny optimal solution is called the local Kemenization of the ranking.

So, this process gives us the core idea of the rank aggregation mechanism we’re using: We pick a starting point according to some heuristic (I’ll explain the heuristic we’re using in a later post), and from that starting point calculate its local Kemenisation. This gives us a ranking which is guaranteed to satisfy the generalised Condorcet condition, and thus likely to be a good ranking, but takes into account whatever our heuristic thought was important as well – this can matter a lot for cases where there is ambiguity in the ranking data.

This entry was posted in Numbers are hard, programming on by .

One thought on “Rank aggregation basics: Local Kemeny optimisation

  1. Pingback: » Programming languages: quality, popularity, and versatility Interesting Question

Comments are closed.